Date:
Fri, 9 Dec 2005 10:44:47 +1100
From:
Neil Foster
Subject:
Kirby J. in the High Court of Australia
Dear
Jason et al;
Thanks
for taking up the serious point in this (I've really enjoyed reading
the other emails about the case-name stuff as well, however!) I
agree with what you say about the way that Lord Atkin was reasoning
in Donoghue v Stevenson to some extent. He clearly was
saying: on the one hand morality (informed by the Christian perspective
of Jesus' story of the Good Samaritan) would require us to go to
extraordinary lengths to care for others; but the law does not go
so far.
However,
the very concept that we are called on to care for ("in
some circumstances", as Kirby J says) others as our neighbours
can be seen to be supported by the Scriptural principles mentioned.
It is just the circumstances that differ in the legal analysis from
that of the principles of life generally.
We
could probably debate the legitimacy of the reasoning in Lord Atkin's
judgement forever, but re-reading it this year I was impressed with
the subtlety of it. After all, he was starting with the handicap
of the recent high-level Scottish decision in Mullen v Barr
which was precisely on point except for the species of the deceased
inhabitant of the ginger-beer bottle. He could have spent all his
time pointing out why the Scottish court in Mullen v Barr
got it wrong. But he starts from the other end, the end of morality.
Look at what we would have to support if we simply turned morality
into law - the costly and outrageous love of the Samaritan. No,
we won’t go that far - we’ll spell out limits
to the principle of morality using the notion of foreseeability.
So instead of being seen as the judge who expands liability,
he looks (at least at this point in his judgement) like a judge
who limits liability which morality would otherwise impose.
But
I would still support Kirby J's comment that this very idea of concern
for neighbour is a valid principle, and is to some extent being
undermined by the attitude of "watch out for yourself"
which seems to underlie some recent decisions of courts in Australia,
at least. While I don't necessarily disagree with the final result
in Junkovic, it seems at least arguable that when you invite
other people onto your premises so that you can profit from their
purchasing your goods, then a few moments' consideration of whether
there are aspects of your premises that should be attended to is
not unreasonable.
Incidentally
I think I agree with your view that the aim of the tort system should
be to correct injustice. I think it is arguably "just",
however, for someone who is proposing to make (even a small) profit
out of others to do (even a bit) to guard against the others being
hurt when they come on the premises.
Regards
Neil Foster
Neil
Foster
Lecturer & LLB Program Convenor
School of Law
Faculty of Business & Law
University of Newcastle
Callaghan NSW 2308
AUSTRALIA
ph 02 4921 7430
fax 02 4921 6931
>>>
Jason Neyers 9/12/05 3:00 >>>
Colleagues:
While
Neil may find the "impassioned plea" of Kirby compelling,
I do not:
Kirby
J in Neindorf v Junkovic [2005] HCA 75 (8 December 2005)
[86]
To the extent that the Court turns away from the earlier principles,
in my respectful view it endorses notions of selfishness that are
the antithesis of the Atkinian concept of the legal duty that we
all owe, in some circumstances, to each other as "neighbours"
[115]. This is a moral notion, derived originally from Scripture,
that has informed the core concept of the English law of negligence
that we have inherited and developed in Australia. It is the notion
that, in the past, encouraged care and attention for the safety
of entrants on the part of those who invite others onto their premises.
(It also encouraged such persons to procure insurance against risk).
To the extent that these ideas are overthrown, and reversed, this
Court diminishes consideration of accident prevention. (It also
reduces the utility and necessity of insurance). From the point
of view of legal policy, these are not directions in which I would
willingly travel.
Two
points about this passage: 1)
His Lordship’s summary is misleading in that Lord Atkin
made clear that the principle derived from the scripture transmutes
itself from one of (full) morality into one of legality (limited
morality) — it must, otherwise the law would be legitimizing
a Christian theocracy. The key classic difference between the
moral view and the legal being that the legal principle allows
for the very selfishness which Kirby says it denies: you must
not hurt only those things which are already another’s but
you do not have to cater to their needs or render them assistance
to gain anything (see also Palsgraph, Dorset Yacht).
This is clearly not the message that Christ was delivering in
the Scripture. Hence, the private law is not levelling any playing
field or redistributing (as Kirby claims in [85]) but is reasserting
the status quo or correcting.
2)
Kirby makes the classic instrumental mistake in taking the result,
or end product, of having a legal system that corrects injustice,
i.e. accident prevention and loss spreading through insurance, and
turns these into the “purposes” of the law. I doubt
that very few people would agree that the private law should be
doing everything that prevents accidents (beheadings for speeding
or impaired driving anyone?) or more efficiently spreads its losses
(making the government vicariously liable for every accident caused
by a citizen), yet if these are the law’s purposes a rational
judge would pursue them diligently.
The
failure to recognize these two errors are the reasons why Commonwealth
tort law, and more generally private law, is in such a mess and
why ultimately the “impassioned pleas” of Justice Kirby
(in private law cases) are rarely ever persuasive.
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|