Date:
Wed, 10 Dec 2003 10:01:16 -0500
From:
Jason Neyers
Subject:
Mitigation by adoption
Dear
Colleagues,
I
want to thank everyone for their discussion on this issue since
it has really helped me clarify my views.
I
think that these types of cases are ones where the mechanical/surface
application of the law, rather than the casuistic, arguably leads
one down the incorrect path (which is what Allan was poking at,
I think). For example, Andrew asserts that it is obviously unreasonable
to take into account the fact that the plaintiff has not mitigated
or has kept the baby. If this is the case, then it follows that
this fact cannot be taken into account when assessing damages and
she is entitled to financial compensation on the application of
ordinary principles which do not allow set-offs between different
types of damages. (I mean this with no hostility or disrespect to
Andrew or anyone else, btw).
But
this dodges the question of why it is unreasonable to demand mitigation.
I do not know Andrew's answer (since it appears he assumes it is
self-evident) but I will assume that many people would say "because
life is special" and/or that human life cannot be treated as if
it were just any other asset/liability. I can follow that line of
reasoning. But when it comes to assessing damages, the plaintiff
backs away from the implicit assertion that is hidden in the "mitigation
is unreasonable argument" and then asserts that the wrongful birth
is to be treated as if it were just any other legal wrong in which
the normal rules of financial compensation should apply. To be frank,
I find that to be somewhat contradictory. If "life is special" gets
you over the mitigation hump, then it is something that should factor
into the assessment of damages as well.
This
is the approach that Lord Scott employed in Rees
when he worked through the law with a nuanced argument that took
into account the unique nature of human life. This also seems to
be the import of the quote of Gleeson CJ (which Jamie mentioned)
from Cattanach
v Melchior (which I still have to read).
If
on the other hand, life is not so special when it comes to the issue
of damages, then I think one might then ask the plaintiff to mitigate
in the normal way if they now find being a parent unappealing. The
plaintiff would of course then be entitled to the costs, if any,
involved in mitigating as Jennifer suggests.
Sincerely,
Andrew
Robertson wrote:
Fleming notes (9th ed, p 286) that '[t]he burden is on the defendant
to prove that the plaintiff's refusal to mitigate was unreasonable'
and this has now been accepted by the PC as the correct approach
(see Geest
plc v Lansiquot [2003] 1 All ER 383). So, the question here
is whether, the sterilisation having failed and a child having been
conceived, the plaintiffs' decision to keep the child is unreasonable.
Clearly it is not.
--
Jason Neyers
Assistant Professor of Law
Faculty of Law
University of Western Ontario
N6A 3K7
(519) 661-2111 x. 88435
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|