![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
Dear Professor
McInnes,
Thank-you for your response to my first submission to the RDG. Generally,
I agree with many of the points that you made, especially with your elucidation
of the cases as being incoherent and with the point that many Canadian
judges are confused as to juristic reason. I just had a few queries.
1. In your response to my e-mail you stated: "whereas the civilian tradition
permits restitution simply because the defendant has no good claim to
it, the common law tradition requires proof positive as to why the plaintiff
should enjoy relief."
To what group of cases or legal principles are you referring to with
this statement? Are you referring only to the UE cases? If you are, it
hardly seems correct to use a line of thought that I am attacking to prove
that my point is incorrect as a matter of logic. That begs the question.
Also, I don't think that pointing to the cases with the "unjust factors"
of mistake or duress helps your argument much because the presence of
these factors equally shows that the plaintiff did not truly intend the
transfer as a gift or as part of a contract (hence no juristic reason).
Is another body of private law principle that sets up this point? I just
can't think of what it is offhand. It seems as a matter of logic that
if I went to court to ask for a piece of property back, all I would have
to show was that I was the owner/best possessor and that the defendant
had no claim to the property better than my own. Do I have to show "proof
positive" to get relief? If I do, is this requirement based upon principle
or is it merely a procedural requirement / holdover from a more formulaic
era? As applied to an UE claim, it seems as a matter of logic that I should
merely have to prove that the deprivation came from me and that you are
not entitled to it. What does the intermediate "proof positive" step add,
except a layer of discretion that judges can use to withhold relief on
the "basis of amorphous notions of justice and equity"?
2. In response to my e-mail you stated: " it seems preferable to endorse
a formulation of the third element of the cause of action in unjust enrichment
that provides the courts with as much assistance as possible... And in
that regard, an approach that categorizes the factors that historically
have supported restitution in the common law tradition (but that allows
for incremental and analogical extensions) seems far preferable to an
approach that simply requires a judge to determine whether or not some
(undefined) juristic reason exists."
While this is a valid practical point (one proved by quite a few strange
judgments), it says little about the logical implications of the juristic
reason approach to UE. I could simply answer back that judges only need
to be better informed as to what a juristic reason is. It is not a nebulous
concept, as you implicitly claim, but simply one that is misunderstood
by outcome and policy driven Canadian judges. If they understood the concept
as it was meant to be understood (i.e as it is understood by [Quebec]
civilians) there would be no problem whatsoever. It seems to me that there
is an equal danger that Canadian judges will use the concept of "unjust
factors" to achieve their desired policy goals.
Jason W. Neyers <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |