![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
This is a follow-up
to the e-mail of Dr. Gerhard Dannemann where he suggests that in English
law it is not helpful to resort to "obvious" or "failure of basis" reasoning
to deal with issues such as Lord Archers in a common law system since any
change in UE will affect contract in tort in difficult ways. In that mail
he commented that he might be interested in hearing how Canadian courts
deal with the problems that he outlined.
My answer, as the debate with Prof. McInnes demonstrates, is that one
cannot say how Canadian courts deal with these problems because one cannot
with certainty say how these courts will deal with unjust enrichment (i.e.
unjust factors versus absence of juristic reason).
With that in mind, I would like to answer some of your challenges to
the "juristic reason" analysis in a common law system (such as England
or Canada) because I don't think that many of them are as problematic
as they first appear. Many terms have been used to describe this method
of UE reasoning in your letter but I am of the opinion that the "juristic
reason" terminology is the best with which to continue.
Challenge 1: "Illegal contracts and quantum meruit"
If it is true that there is a public policy (or rule of public order)
which denies the enforcement of illegal contracts then I see no reason
why this same public policy would not apply to a claim under UE as well.
All it would take is one case to apply the public policy in the new situation.
Hardly, an upheaval in the legal system.
Challenge 2: "The procedural rule that a judgment is final after all
possibilities of appeal have been exhausted becomes equally irrelevant
if we allow unjust enrichment claims to return payments made under this
judgment while leaving the judgment itself intact".
Your point is well taken but under the "juristic reason" analysis a judgment
is a sufficient juristic reason to deny recover. I cannot think of a better
juristic reason than to say there is a judgment justifying the deprivation.
Challenge 3: "The combination of a condictio indebiti with the lack of
gratuitous contracts is more problematic." The example: " Somebody agrees
to help a friend to paint his rooms, and after having fallen out with
the friend, claims a quantum meruit."
If I understand your hypothetical correctly the friend was not labouring
under a mistake as no consideration was to be expected. Under the "juristic
reason" analysis the answer is simple. There is no UE in this case because
there is a juristic reason justifying the deprivation -- the friend intended
his labour as a gift. A gift is a juridical act in the common law as well.
One does not need the idea of gratuitous contacts to analyse this fact
pattern and conclude that there should be no recovery.
Challenge 4: "form requirements"
I think I need more information to comment.
Challenge 5: "Gaming & Betting Contracts"
See answer to challenge 2.
Moreover, what is the problem with the legislator intervening to make
this an unactionable contract (similar to the statute of frauds, which
is hardly a new innovation)? I do not think that the principles of the
common law, or formulations of these principles, should be denied at the
onset simply because our public policy interventions will have to be tweaked
to account for the evolution. This is especially the case where the change
is coherent and (possibly) conceptually better. For example, would you
say that concurrent liability in tort and contract should be denied as
a principle of common law (if it is the correct principle) merely because
there might be difficulties with existing statutes or rules of civil procedure
that were drafted before this conclusion. To do so, in my opinion, would
be to put pragmatism and ingrained practice before principle and logic.
Jason W. Neyers <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |