![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
My
response to Nicholas Briggs (requesting arguments in support of estoppel)
is that there is a need in the law of restitution for a broad, flexible
defence which is not limited in its scope to identifying payments causally
connected to the receipt of the mistaken payment. Whether such a broad defence
is applied using estoppel principles, or by treating change of position
itself as a broad equitable defence allowing for a balancing of the equities
between the parties (as the NZ CA did in Bank of NZ v Waitaki [1999] 2 NZLR
211) may not be overly important (one benefit of the latter approach is
that it does not require the identification of a "representation" by the
payer; one benefit of estoppel is that it may be more grounded in established
principle and authorities). The important thing is that the courts should
take into account factors such as the following.
(1) The emotional distress and turmoil induced by a
request to repay money, say, many years after its receipt. (Cf Commonwealth
v Verwayen, where some members of the HC of Australia considered that
the detriment suffered if a representor were not estopped from denying
the representation would include the "stress and anxiety" suffered by
the representee if the representation/assumption were not made good:
eg Gaudron J 170 CLR 394 at 487). I would think that in Australia, at
least, the estoppel defence would not necessarily operate in an all
or nothing way, the courts being able to shape the remedy according
to the minimum equity needed to do justice between the parties. This
may mean that in some circumstances, the remedy may be limited to reversing
the detriment incurred in reliance upon the representation. It does
not mean, however, that the detriment suffered in consequence of the
denial of the representation is necessarily limited to and measured
by the financial losses incurred in reliance upon or causally connected
to, the receipt of the money.
(2) Related to this point is the fact that an unqualified
and authoritative representation may lead payees to hold expectations
the denial of which may have detrimental consequences which can not
necessarily be measured by reference to financial expenses incurred
(but which detriment is more than merely the disappointment of not having
one's expectation fulfilled.
(3) Any negligence of both payers and payees must also
be relevant (cf Waitaki). It would be odd if in our system of law, carelessness
(or "contributory negligence"?) were not a relevant consideration. The
theory that even gross negligence on the part of the payer in making
or insisting upon the payment is irrelevant has always struck me as
counter-intuitive.
(4) Any other relevant factors, such as "risk allocation"
between the parties and relative fault, need to be considered (Thomas
J in Waitaki at 229). In Scottish Equity itself, the gross negligence
of the payer and the unqualified representation that the payee was entitled
to the payment ought to have been taken into account in balancing the
equities between the parties. I for one do not think that the payee
ought to be liable to repay the money used for mortgage payments in
that case. At least in relation to those payments, the payee's expectations
ought to be made good, for if they are not and the payee is required
to repay them, I think it is accurate to say that the payee will be
worse off than if the mistaken payment had never been received. There
are some considerable similarities to Verwayen's case.
In relation to the point made by Robert Stevens:
However, having read the following passage [in Scottish
Equitable] it seems to me that it can now be argued that the existence
of the defence of change of position prevents the defendant, in the
usual case, from establishing that he has detrimentally relied upon
the claimant's statement: 'A pays £1000 to B, representing to him "I have
carefully checked all the figures and this is all yours". B spends
£250 on a party and puts £750 in the bank. A discovers that he has
made a mistake and owed B nothing. He learns that B has spent £250
and he asks B to repay £750. B: "You are estopped by your representation on which
I have acted to my detriment." A: "You have not acted to your detriment. You have
had a good party, and at my expense, because I cannot recover the
£250 back from you."' In my view, the Court of Appeal seem to be saying that
estoppel does operate in this situation, but is limited to the minimum
equity to do justice: ie there is no detriment which arises from denying
the representation as to B's right to £750 only. This must be right
(and see also Fung and Ho Note in 117 LQR 14). But what the Court of
Appeal does not recognise (but which the NZ CA in using change of position
and the Australian HC in its development of estoppel do recognise) is
that the minimum equity to do justice between the parties cannot be
determined merely by reference to expenditure incurred which is causally
connected to the receipt (to repeat the point I made above).
Joachim Dietrich -----Original Message----- You can find a full transcript on
Casetrack.com. The case number is A2/00/0418 or for those of you who
are familiar with the neutral citation [2001] EWCA CIV 369. The CA have
ducked the issue of whether estoppel survives the defence of change
of position. The Court said that it would leave that question for another
case (curious as there was a direct finding of fact at first instance
in relation to estoppel). A member of my chambers shall be running the
argument that estoppel does survive. The Court of Appeal adjourned the
hearing pending the outcome of Derby and have acknowledged that the
argument is live. The matter is called National Westminster Bank Plc
v Somer International and is due to be heard in the Court of Appeal
on 9 April 2000. All arguments to support estoppel gratefully received.
<== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |