![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
Dear Lionel,
Normally an enrichment and corresponding
deprivation are unjust only if the factors which make them so are present
at the time of the transfer. However, there is clearly a qualification
to this in the case of failure of basis. In that case, there is a kind
of seed of injustice in place at the time of the transfer (a mutual
understanding as to its basis), which germinates if the basis fails.
As an aside, does this potentially show that the reason
for restitution in the failure of basis cases is not unjust enrichment
but rather the breach of contract (followed by reliance/restitution damages)
or an implied condition of the contract (if X not true we are not to be
bound)? :)
In regards to Mack, perhaps a possible line of
attack might be based on the special nature of the government (i.e. as
an entity which exists for the sole purpose of promoting the public good
as embodied in the Constitution). The argument is as follows: Although
there was a juristic reason for the enrichment at the time, it is not
open to the government today to argue this juristic reason since to do
so would force it to take a position (one can be discriminated on the
basis of race) which is now constitutionally impermissible. Such a limitation
would be similar to the argument in Jane Doe v. Metropolitan Police
(1990 Div Ct.), Roncarelli v. Duplessis (1959 SCR) and City
of Kamloops v. Neilsen (1984 SCC) that there are inherent/implicit
limits on the exercise of state power such that some lines of defence
are impermissible/irrational for the government to take (in Jane Doe's
case that women 'overreacted' to fears of sexual assault and thus did
not have to be warned by police of rapists in the area). I think support
for such a position can be found in the Idea of Private Law (see the discussion
surrounding nonfeasance) and in the Weinribs' new article "Constitutional
Values and Private Law in Canada" in Human Rights in Private Law
(2001 Hart).
What do you think?
My initial analysis of the unjust enrichment claim was
that restitution was impossible unless the legislation could be shown
to be invalid at the time the tax was paid, either due to inconsistency
with some then-existing superior norm, or by the enactment of some later
norm with retroactive effect. Both of these arguments were made, but they
are very difficult. The former has to be based on international law, and
the latter on the Charter. The SCC has held that s. 15 of the Charter,
which came into effect in 1985, does not have retroactive effect:
Another argument that might be tried in relation to
attacking the validity of the tax would be the implied "bill of rights"
theory (i.e., there are certain actions which are ultra vires either
level of government even without a Charter) which would count on
as a "then-existing superior norm". If I remember correctly the implied
"bill of rights" theory was superseded by the Bill of Rights and
then the Charter but that does not mean that it could not be resurrected
to deal with earlier cases.
Just some thoughts.
Jason
Lionel Smith wrote:
I do not think that the case of Mack
v Canada has been mentioned on the RDG yet. This is a potential class
action arising out of the imposition, during the years 1885-1923, of
a 'head tax' on immigrants to Canada from China. (During the period
1923-1947 Chinese immigrants were effectively excluded from Canada.)
The plaintiffs put forward three causes
of action: (a) two violations of s. 15 of the Charter, which prohibits
governmental discrimination; (b) a violation of customary international
law; (c) unjust enrichment. The Ontario Supreme Court of Justice ((2001),
55 O.R. (3d) 113) and the Court
of Appeal ((2002), 60 O.R. (3d) 373 (C.A.)) have struck out the
statement of claim as disclosing no reasonable cause of action. Leave
to appeal has been sought [2002] S.C.C.A. No. 476.
Some claims are based on argued present
(or recent) injustices, particularly a form of discrimination in that
the government has made reparations to Japanese Canadians interned during
WWII but has not made any reparations in this case. The unjust enrichment
claim, however, is based on the head tax payments.
I am giving a paper this weekend at
a conference arising out of the litigation. My initial analysis of the
unjust enrichment claim was that restitution was impossible unless the
legislation could be shown to be invalid at the time the tax was paid,
either due to inconsistency with some then-existing superior norm, or
by the enactment of some later norm with retroactive effect. Both of
these arguments were made, but they are very difficult. The former has
to be based on international law, and the latter on the Charter. The
SCC has held that s. 15 of the Charter, which came into effect in 1985,
does not have retroactive effect: Benner
v Canada (Secretary of State), [1997] 1 S.C.R. 358, 143 D.L.R. (4th)
577. It is clear that s. 15 cannot make governments liable for harm
caused by pre-1985 discrimination.
However, Benner says that while s.
15 does not work retroactively, it operates against ongoing discrimination
which continues in force after 1985, even if some of the crucial facts
(in Benner's case, the circumstances of his birth) occurred before 1985.
This has led me to consider the following argument. Normally an enrichment
and corresponding deprivation are unjust only if the factors which make
them so are present at the time of the transfer. However, there is clearly
a qualification to this in the case of failure of basis. In that case,
there is a kind of seed of injustice in place at the time of the transfer
(a mutual understanding as to its basis), which germinates if the basis
fails. See A. Burrows, The Law of Restitution, 2 ed., 332-333, commenting
on this unusual feature. Following the pattern of failure of basis,
I wonder whether it is possible to argue that a transfer based on discriminatory
legislation might not be unjustified at the time it is made, but when
subsequently a constitutional enactment is passed which forbids governmental
discrimination (including by legislation), the seed of injustice germinates
and the transfer becomes unjustified. This ends up actually following
Benner, because you can say that you are not relying on a retroactive
operation of s. 15, but only on a continuing state of affairs which
is contrary to s. 15, namely the ongoing enrichment of the state, acquired
through overtly discriminatory legislation. This would preserve the
result that past harm caused by discrimination is not compensable due
to the coming into force of s. 15, since we do not want to make conduct
wrongful retroactively; but it would distinguish the case of unjust
enrichment, which does not turn on wrongdoing. And just as in the case
of failure of basis, an argument that the enrichment has been dissipated
between the transfer and the completion of the injustice (or later)
would be for the defendant to make (and would not anyway arise on a
defendant's striking out motion). Again following the example of failure
of basis, the limitation period would not start to run until 1985 (or
maybe even from Benner in 1997 on a discoverability basis).
I thought this case might spark some
discussion, and in any event I would be grateful for any thoughts on
my ideas as outlined above.
The judgments, the legislation, and
other related material including pleadings is available on the conference
web site, http://www.law.utoronto.ca/conferences/reparations.html
Lionel
-- <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |