![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
Charles,
I hope I haven't fallen into he trap of failing to keep
separate the issues of the wrongdoers' liability and the extent of that
liability to P from the issues of how to apportion financial responsibility
between the wrongdoers. You are both right and wrong, I think, to point
out that it's a non-sequitur to argue merely from the proposition that
the fiduciary and assistant are jointly liable to P, as joint wrongdoers,
that as between themselves they necessarily ought to be equally responsible
for the loss. Canadian authority, in fact, doesn't require that conclusion.
The nature of the duty breached by each of the wrongdoers is relevant
to the apportionment. I suspect that if I searched, I'd find a case where
the fact that T1 was the fiduciary and T2 the assistant resulted in T1
having a greater share. On the other hand, I think it just as likely we'd
find sufficient involvement on the part of T2, even if not a fiduciary,
to move the significance of T2's conduct sufficiently close to the level
of T1's that the apportionments wouldn't be significantly different.
My point, though, is that on the assumption P1 and P2
are joint wrongdoers, it seems to me there's a logical inconsistency in
that result (the greater share to T1) if the central basis for apportionment
is causative potency. That inconsistency exists because, as joint wrongdoers,
the conduct of one is the conduct of all, if apply the consequences of
that deeming even in apportionment. To eliminate the inconsistency, we
have to add, in the apportionment context, that the deeming of the conduct
does not carry with it the moral approbation. I see no principled reason
preventing that approach. The issues at the apportionment stage are sufficiently
different that principle doesn't require that T2 always be deemed to be
treated as if T2 had actually acted as T1 did. It's just that, if one
does that, I think logic requires the realization that the consequence
is inconsistent with the causative potency of all of the acts which the
law deems to be T2's. Put another way, you are apportioning financial
responsibility based only on the causative potency of T2's own acts. Again,
there's nothing wrong with that distinction, particularly given the underpinning
of the contribution remedy in UE. It just needs to be made clear that
that is what is happening.
Anyway, I rather suspect that in most cases of the sort
you are describing, we would have a finding that the assistant's conduct
creates direct liability on the assistant and that that conduct was causative,
given the current summary of the law required for T2 to be liable in such
circumstances. See the summary in Commercial
Union Life Assurance Co. of Canada v. John Ingle Insurance Group Inc.,
2002 CanLII 45028 (Ont CA) at para 2-4 where the Ont CA summarizes the
current law relating to the "nature of the breach of trust required to
impose liability on a stranger for knowing assistance". I haven't thought
it through but, on first blush, it seems to me that Canada's retention
of the broad approach to the principles of tort liability that flows from
Anns v Merton, which England has (somewhat ?) resiled from, might
be relevant to explaining our approach.
I've been lax, the past two plus decades, in keeping
up with cases that might affect how one meshes the traditional consequences
of joint wrongdoing with apportionment legislation insofar as those consequences
affect apportionment as between the wrongdoers. I'm reasonably certain
the issue, put that way, is often considered; at least because there is
a tendency in Canadian courts to say that the apportionment legislation
means its no longer necessary to consider whether the wrongdoers are joint,
so long as there's a finding that their conduct caused the same damages.
(We've generally managed to avoid the damage / damages problem, so far.)
I assume that one or more of the members of this list will know, of hand,
if there are Canadian cases where the court has specifically considered
how the apportionment is affected by the fact that T1 was the actual fiduciary
and T2 merely the assistant. CGU doesn't assist, really, because
the person who would have been T2 in your construct (John Ingle) wasn't
found liable at all based on Canadian law and the conduct of the other
person who was a stranger to the trust was sufficiently egregious as to
create direct, personal liability for that conduct.
Regards,
David
----- Original Message ----- Dear David
I'll certainly go back and read Atiyah's
piece: thanks for the reference. But my snap answer so far as the trustee/dishonest
assistant example is concerned is that this is one of those rare situations
contemplated by Atiyah where
it can be clearly demonstrated that
the assistance of one of the parties made no difference to the result.
Under English law at least, the causation
rules for dishonest assistance are unusual because the courts have recognised
liability under this head as a kind of civil secondary liability analogous
to criminal secondary liability - a step which they refused to take
at common law in Credit
Lyonnais v ECGD [2000] 1 AC 164. See most recently Ultraframe
(UK) Ltd v Fielding [2005] EWHC 1638 (Ch) [1506] (Lewison J).
Hence, to establish liability all
that needs to be proved against a dishonest assistant is that he did
something which made the defaulting fiduciary's breach of duty easier
than it would otherwise have been: Brown
v Bennett [1999] 1 BCLC 649 at 659. Hence he may be liable
even if the loss would have occurred anyway.
On your argument, it follows from
the fact that a dishonest assistant D1 and a defaulting fiduciary D2
are jointly and severally liable to the principal, that when it comes
to apportion between D1 and D2, the law must deem them to have caused
the principal's loss jointly and thus to the same extent.
But I believe this to be a non sequitur.
As between D1 and the principal, the law wishes to make D1 liable to
the same extent as D2, even though the causative impact of his actions
has been less, because he is a very bad guy, subjectively dishonest.
But it does not follow from this that as between D1 and D2, the law
must apportion as though the causative impact of their actions was identical.
<== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |