Date:
Tue, 8 Feb 2005 18:07:11
From:
Robert Stevens
Subject:
Remoteness
The
HL decision in Jackson
v RBS that Jason mentioned yesterday does not take the
law on remoteness very much further. However, it has made me think
again about remoteness in contract damages.
In
the tort of negligence, it is possible to justify a rule which says
that only reasonably foreseeable harm is recoverable as required
by the fault principle. The defendant is only at fault in relation
to the loss which was a reasonably foreseeable consequence of his
actions (cf Wagon Mound (No 1)).
Where
a (strict) contractual obligation is breached, requiring the loss
to be within the reasonable contemplation of the defendant as a
serious possibility at the time of contracting, cannot be justified
by appealing to the fault principle. The duty breached is strict.
As between the party in breach of contract and the innocent party
who should bear the unforeseeable loss? Stating that it is 'fair'
that the innocent party does so doesn't provide an explanation.
It
may be that the remoteness rule in contract serves the useful aim
of encouraging disclosure of the risk of harm ("I should warn you
that I don't have a spare shaft for my mill and you mustn't be late").
But this cannot be a sufficient justification for the rule as it
applies where the claimant doesn't know of the unusual loss he might
suffer (ie where he has nothing to disclose). Disallowing the recovery
of loss which could not be foreseen by either party cannot be justified
by a policy in favour of disclosure.
It
could be argued that the remoteness rule encourages people to contract
as they know they are not entering into open-ended obligations to
pay unlimited damages. On the other hand, it could be said to discourage
bargaining as you may be forced to bear a large loss due to the
deliberate breach of the counter-party. There is no such thing as
a free lunch - someone has to bear the loss.
Another
explanation comes from Pothier (whose formulation of the rule was
indirectly the source for the formulation in Hadley v Baxendale).
He said that only losses within the defendant's reasonable contemplation
could be recovered as it was only those which the defendant could
be considered to have consented to be liable for. However, is it
sensible to speak of the defendant only having accepted the risk
of having to pay for foreseeable damages? The parties bargain for
performance, not damages and it is no longer usual to attempt to
justify contractual damages as being what the parties bargained
for (cf Holmes). Does the fact that I know you might suffer a particular
loss as a result of my breach of contract mean that I am consenting
to make good that loss if I breach the contract?
If
the justifications for the remoteness rules in contract and the
tort of negligence are different this may help us to explain why
the content of those rules differ and how they inter-relate where
liability is concurrent. Certainly the justification for the rule
in WM (no 1) doesn't seem to apply to Hadley v Baxendale,
I am just not sure what the appropriate justification for H
v B is. Further which justification, if any, tells us the degree
of probability with which the risk of harm must be reasonably contemplated?
Not unlikely? Probable? Serious possibility?
Views?
Robert
Stevens
Barrister
Oxford University
<<<<
Previous Message ~ Index ~ Next
Message >>>>>
|