![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
At 17:33 22/11/99
-0000, "Jonathon Moore" wrote:
We seem to be having trouble moving away from
answering the question "If event X happens, what legal result follows?"
by saying "It's obvious!" without more. I think that before you studied unjust enrichment, the answer would have
been obvious to you too. No doubt the reason is capable of elaboration
in words if some purpose were served by it. But what we are discussing
is whether digesting the "unjust enrichment" theory has made our under-
standing of the legal system better (as you contend) or worse (as I contend).
If it were *not* obvious to a particular person that the money should
be returned, why should they be any more convinced on hearing that the
return was mandated by some "principle of unjust enrichment" ?
By the way, how *do* you explain the fact that when a criminal conviction
is quashed, we let the defendant out of jail ? Is that "unjust enrichment",
too ? And what would you say to someone who didn't find it obvious that
he should be let out ?
The Germans would, I think, say 1. We say 2.
In either case, the claim is one where the law raises a right of recovery
in order to prevent the defendant being unjustly enriched. The English legal system got by for most of its history without invoking
the idea of "unjust enrichment". How does describing it as "unjust enrichment"
improve our understanding of it ? Or are you falling back on saying that
*that* is obvious ?
The mere fact that the older cases mentioned
by Charles Mitchell did not use the words "unjust enrichment" hardly vindicate
Hedley's view that the cases had nothing to do with that well-recognised
(though only recently articulated) principle. I am afraid that in a precedent-based system, the "mere fact" that the
concept is not mentioned cannot be dismissed so easily. You should be
more wary of citing cases for propositions which were not mentioned in
them. I realise that some introductory textbooks cite Moses v. Macfarlane
as providing some support for the theory of unjust enrichment, but that
argument is a rather tortuous one. It is wrong to cite the case as if
it provided unequivocal support for the theory; the "mere facts" are against
this.
So we return to the point at which we started.
I say that the right of recovery is raised by the law in order to reverse
the defendant's unjust enrichment. He says that the explanation of the
obligation is so obvious it does not need explaining. Isn't it interesting that you keep on attacking me for saying it is
obvious, yet you don't deny that it *is* obvious ?
I say again : If it were not *already* obvious to a given person that
the money is recoverable, how would a reference to "unjust enrichment"
help ? Bear in mind, in answering, that most people who talk about "unjust
enrichment" are not making a moral judgment, but merely saying that the
enrichment is reversible. What, then, does "unjust enrichment" add ?
Steve Hedley
=================================================== Christ's College Cambridge CB2 3BU <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |