![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
Hello all,
The recent vigorous debate on this list has discussed
many important structural and taxonomic matters. Mentioned in passing
has been Prof Birks' recanting of the perfect quadration of restitution
and unjust enrichment, his conversion to the multi-causal nature of the
response of restitution, and his consequent espousal of unjust enrichment
as an appropriate for the subject. Let me take up that point by means
of quoting an extract from something I've just written:
__________ Begin Extract __________
Just as the courts have rejected the implied contract
fiction and begun to coalesce around a vision of a law of restitution
founded upon … the principle against unjust enrichment, academic debate
has, almost inevitably, begun to call it into question. For example, Birks,
whose work was so influential in the developments sketched above, was
once of the view that "Restitution and unjust enrichment identify exactly
the same area of law. The one term quadrates with the other". [fn96] That
is, if the cause of action is the unjust enrichment of the defendant at
the expense of the plaintiff, the remedy is restitution to the plaintiff
from the defendant of the amount of that unjust enrichment. However, he
has since recanted of this quadration. He now [fn 97] believes that restitution
in the sense of giving back can be a response to an obligation arising
not only from an unjust enrichment but also from consent (as where the
defendant agreed to the return), and from a wrong (because restitution
for the wrong is a consequence of the law relating to the wrong itself),
[fn 98] so that to confine the meaning of the word "restitution" [fn 99]
to a response to unjust enrichment is to ignore that the natural meaning
of the word restitution can include the other responses he identifies.
For him, the remedy for this instability is to adopt "unjust enrichment"
as a more appropriate title for the subject than restitution. This, unfortunately,
muddies waters which have only recently begun to run clear. The stability
which Birks requires of the phrase "unjust enrichment" is illusory, because,
though Birks would deny this, the phrase "unjust enrichment" can be used
in the law in manners which are neither pejorative nor as substantively
precise as he would insist; indeed, there is a spectrum [100] along which
lie various visions of unjust enrichment, from the very technical descriptive
principle advocated by Birks and adopted by the Irish, English and Australian
courts, through the slightly more open-textured prescriptive principle
adopted by the Canadian courts, and the related but less technical understandings
of the principle, [fn101] often expressed in 'equitable' terms, [fn 102]
to much looser senses [fn 103] and ultimately to pejorative dismissals
of unfettered palm tree justice or worse. If the word "restitution" is,
as Birks puts it, multi-causal, then the phrase "unjust enrichment" is
equally multi-faceted. In both cases, there are many possible meanings,
and the law seems to have chosen one meaning in each case; so that the
phrase "unjust enrichment" describes a cause of action for which the word
"restitution" describes its remedy. [fn 104] In so doing, it would simply
be another example of the law ascribing to words stable legal definitions
which differ in some way either from their meanings in ordinary speech
or from other legally plausible meanings. Though the natural meaning of
restitution might extend beyond unjust enrichment, and the possible usage
of unjust enrichment might in its turn extend beyond restitution, nevertheless,
their overlap indisputably defines a relatively stable field of the law
of obligations. It is not now necessary to undo what has only recently
been done, and done well.
96. Birks, p 17.
97. See, eg, Birks "Misnomer" in Cornish, Nolan, O'Sullivan
and Virgo (eds) Restitution. Past, Present and Future (Hart Publishing,
Oxford, 1998) p 1; Birks "The Law of Unjust Enrichment: A Millennial Resolution"
[1998] Singapore JLS 318; Birks "Equity, Conscience and Unjust Enrichment"
(1999) 23 Melb ULR 1; Birks "The Law of Restitution at the End of an Epoch"
(1999) 28 UWALR 13; see also Swadling "What is the Law of Restitution
About: Four Categorical Errors" in Cornish, Nolan, O'Sullivan and Virgo
(eds) Restitution. Past, Present and Future (Hart Publishing, Oxford,
1998) p 331. However, (inevitably ?), this recantation has proved controversial;
see, eg, Tettenborn "Misnomer - a Response to Professor Birks" in in Cornish,
Nolan, O'Sullivan and Virgo (eds) Restitution. Past, Present and Future
(Hart Publishing, Oxford, 1998) p 32; McInnes "Restitution, Unjust Enrichment,
and the Perfect Quadration Thesis" [1999] RLR 118.
98. In fact, Birks argues that as a matter of taxonomy,
the law of obligations divides into four: those obligations which arise
from consent, wrongs, and unjust enrichment, and those which fall into
a fourth miscellany; for him, the doctrines which protect the reliance
interest at common law identified at various points in this comment (see,
eg, text with and in nn 123-126 below) provide an example within this
fourth category. Consistently with his view that restitution can be a
response to an obligation arising not only from an unjust enrichment but
also from consent and from a wrong, he also argues that it can be a response
to events in the miscellany: see, eg, his discussion of Macmillan v Bishopsgate
Investment Trust (No 3) [1996] 1 All ER 585 (CA) in Birks "Property and
Unjust Enrichment: Categorical Truths" [1997] NZLR 623 (on this piece,
see also n 108 below).
99. That is, restitution at private law; alternative
legal usages of the word restitution in family law and criminal law are
not in issue here.
100. See, generally, Dietrich Restitution. A New Perspective
(Federation Press, Sydney, 1998) pp 10-17; and Virgo pp 6-10, 49-55.
101. See, eg, Friedmann "Valid, Voidable, Qualified and
Non-Existing Obligations: An Alternative Perspective on the Law of Restitution"
in Burrows (ed) Essays on the Law of Restitution (Oxford, 1991) p 247,
distinguishing between technical and related non-technical usages of the
phrase "unjust enrichment".
102. This may be what Lord Clyde had in mind in Banque
Financière de la Cité v Parc (Battersea) [1999] 1 AC
221 (HL) when he said that "the principle of unjust enrichment … is equitable
in the sense that it seeks to secure a fair and just determination of
the rights of the parties concerned in the case" ([1999] 1 AC 221, 237;
though it should be noted that in the same case, Lord Steyn and Lord Hoffmann
took the more precise technical approach; see text with and in n 69 above).
103. An excellent example of such a looser usage is provided
by Prof Atiyah. Writing in 1979, when he perceived "little sign … of any
wholehearted acceptance by English lawyers of a new branch of the law
entitled the Law of Restitution, and based on unjust enrichment ideas"
Prof Atiyah saw the notion of unjust enrichment as simply "an important
underlying idea … operating interstitially in all branches of the law"
(Atiyah The Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract (Oxford, 1979) p 768);
however, the argument in the text is that decisions in the House of Lords,
as well as the Supreme Court of Canada, the High Court of Australia, and
of course the Irish Supreme Court, demonstrate that this view has been
overtaken by just such an acceptance.
104. Or, perhaps more accurately, the word "restitution"
describes that pattern of its various remedies. For an important discussion
of restitutionary remedies, arguing that a distinct remedial focus, when
placed in constructive partnership with the existing debate about causes
of action arising from unjust enrichment, can be a fertile source of understanding
about the nature and content of restitutionary rights, see Barker "Rescuing
Remedialism in Unjust Enrichment Law: Why Remedies are Right" [1998] CLJ
301.
__________ End Extract ___________
The extract is from O'Dell "Bricks and Stones and the
Structure of the Law of Restitution" (1998) 20 DULJ (ns) 101, 119-121.
Though it has a nominal 1998 publication date, it has in fact only recently
been published as part of rescue operation for the DULJ. And now for the
shameless plug. In "Bricks and Stones ..." I consider at inordinate length
the Bricklayers' Hall case [1996] 1 IR 468; [1996] 2 ILRM 547 (SC); [1996]
RLR ß 134, and conclude that, in many ways, the case is modern re-run
of Moses v Macferlan (1760) 2 Burr 1005; 97 ER 976. In the forthcoming
RLR, I summarize the article as follows:
The author argues that the judgments of Budd J at first
instance and of Keane J on appeal are of the first importance, not only
in Ireland but in the common law world, for the development of the law
of restitution based upon a principle against unjust enrichment, the genesis
of which is often traced back to the judgment of Lord Mansfield in Moses
v Macferlan. And those judgments have done much to clarify the ambit of
res judicata as a defence to a claim, not only in restitution, but more
generally in the law. Though there were other routes which they could
have chosen to take, which the author discusses [and it is in this discussion
that the above extract appears] and rejects, the judgments in the Bricklayers'
Hall case establish that the signposts on the current route pose four
enquiries which are then applied in the article to the case itself, concluding
that the enrichment was unjust because the overpayment was both a mistaken
payment and one in respect of a consideration which had failed. The author
argues that these conclusions point the way to the development of the
action for mistake to reach mistakes of law, and to the development of
the action for failure of consideration to reach partial failures and
non-contractual bases, and that important theoretical and practical differences
justify treating them as separate causes of action. In the High Court,
Budd J considered that change of position could have provided a defence,
and his judgment raises the prospect, considered by the author, that Irish
law recognises a justice-related rather than a more limited and more principled
enrichment-related version of the defence. In the Supreme Court, the claim
was dismissed for res judicata, but the author argues that cause of action
estoppel, issue estoppel, estoppel by omission, and abuse of process,
properly did not apply on the facts either of the Bricklayers' Hall case
or of Moses v Macferlan, though public policy or the defence of enrichment
pursuant to obligation would seem to justify the dismissal of the plaintiff's
claim in the Bricklayers Hall case. Finally, in the High Court, Budd J
seemed to hold that the defendant would hold the unjust enrichment on
constructive trust for the plaintiff, but the author argues that unjust
enrichment would have given rise simply to a personal obligation to make
restitution, that there must be something more (such as the Westdeutsche
formulation ([1996] AC 669 (HL) 705 per Lord Browne-Wilkinson)) or something
else (such as a resulting trust) to justify a proprietary obligation to
hold the sum on trust, and that it is an open question whether such an
additional matter was properly to be found in the remedial constructive
trust either in principle or on the facts.
If this summary has whetted anyone's appetite, I'll happily
send an offprint in reply to a request, though given my usual degree of
efficiency, this should read that I'll happily *eventually* send an offprint
in reply to a request. In any event, the point of the message is to prompt
discussion of the multi-causal nature of the word "restitution", the equally
multi-faceted nature of the phrase "unjust enrichment", and the stability
to be obtained not by focussing on one or the other, but upon their overlap.
Best
Eoin.
EOIN O'DELL <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |