![]() |
RDG
online Restitution Discussion Group Archives |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
||||||||||||
|
I retract
my comment about speaking in riddles, and I apologize to Gordon if it was
offensive. But I still think it is better to say what is the rule and why
it makes sense than to interpose maxims and unnecessary concepts like ratification.
I said that my understanding of Gordon's original comment
was that you could recover the profits of a wrong against a wrongdoer
who knew he was acting wrongfully, but not against one who claimed to
be entitled to take whatever it was that he took. That distinction, if
it is to be justified, needs to be justified on its own terms and not
by reference to maxims. I personally do not think it could be justified,
and this becomes clearer when the language of ratification and assumpsit
is stripped away.
Here is another example of what I mean: Gordon said:
Mesne profits are a form of damages - Elliott
v. Boynton [1924] 1 Ch. 236 at 250 per Warrington, L.J. Yet they are
not limited to the demonstrable damage (if any) suffered by the plaintiff,
who may recover under this head the full potential value of the land
to the defendant trespasser for the period of the defendant's wrongful
occupation - Inverugie Investments v. Hackett [1995] 1 W.L.R. 713 P.C.
In my respectful submission, this is not restitution based on a general
theory of unjust enrichment. The trespasser has wrongfully deprived
the plaintiff of the land and so is caught by the maxim, "In odium spoliatoris
omnia praesumuntur", which is, being interpreted, "Everything is presumed
to the prejudice of a plunderer." Accordingly it is presumed that the
full potential value of the land to the trespasser would have been available
to the plaintiff. I agree that this is not restitution based on a general
theory of unjust enrichment. I think it is a disgorgement response which
is available as an alternative to the usual compensatory response, in
the case of trespass to land. Is there a difference between that and what
Gordon says? Yes. What if the defendant was able to prove, as an affirmative
fact, that the plaintiff suffered no loss (even though the defendant profited)?
You might say, in that case, that there would be no claim to the profit.
But let's assume that you want to allow the claim in such a case, because
I think Gordon and I agree on that. On my reasoning you say: because the
claim is measured by the defendant's gain, and does not purport to be
a damages claim for compensation, it is irrelevant that the plaintiff
suffered no loss. But if you want to allow the claim on Gordon's reasoning,
I think you have to say that Gordon's maxim/presumption is an irrebuttable
presumption. But Wigmore showed, a long time ago, that an irrebuttable
presumption is not a presumption at all, it is a rule of substantive law.
In other words, if you say that it is presumed irrebuttably as a matter
of law that the plaintiff suffered a loss which is equal to the defendant's
gain, then what you are really saying is that it is *completely irrelevant*
whether the plaintiff suffered a loss. But then look what you are doing.
You allow the claim on the reasoning that it is compensation for damages;
but it is measured by the defendant's gain, because you have a rule that
the plaintiff's compensation is deemed to be the defendant's gain. That
is what I mean when I speak of riddles: without trying to give offence,
I am only saying that it is an unnecessarily mysterious way of rationalizing
(I am back in Canada so I can spell with z's again) the liability. If
you do not just admit that the claim is measured by the defendant's gain,
you have to use a fictional deemed loss to build a kind of semantic bridge
from compensation for loss to disgorgement of gain.
This is the maxim, which I was taught to
be the warrant for Vice-Chancellor Wood's "second principle", stated
in Frith v. Cartland (1865) 2 H. & M. 417 at 420: "... if a man mixes
trust funds with his own, the whole will be treated as the trust property,
except so far as he may be able to distinguish what is his own". This context is dear to my heart, and I agree that the
rule stated in Frith v Cartland is based on subordinating the interests
of those who wrongfully create evidentiary difficulties. But on the same
reasoning I have deployed above, this is also not a presumption properly
so called, because if it is a presumption it is irrebuttable, and then
it is not really a presumption at all. That is why I have argued that
the tracing rules, contrary to the usual understanding, do not involve
presumptions at all. If they did involve presumptions of honesty on the
part of breaching trustees, there would be no way to justify the "lowest
intermediate balance rule", which was affirmed in Frith v. Cartland itself.
That rule only makes sense if we lose the language of presumptions and
say that *while* every possible inference is drawn against the person
who wrongfully created an evidentiary difficulty, *nonetheless* (because
this is not an irrebuttable presumption of law, just a rule for resolving
difficulties of evidence) we cannot draw inferences which are contrary
to the known facts.
That is the logical limit which is imposed when the reasoning
is based on evidentiary considerations, which is why, in the context of
profitable trespass, you need to explain the liability without reference
to evidentiary considerations (such as deemed losses), unless you do not
want the plaintiff to have the defendant's gain in the case where the
plaintiff can be shown to have suffered no loss.
Lionel <== Previous message Back to index Next message ==> |
||||||||||||
![]() |
![]() |
» » » » » |
|
![]() |
|||||||||
![]() |